This article lists mathematical properties and laws of sets, involving the set-theoretic operations of union, intersection, and complementation and the relations of set equality and set inclusion. It also provides systematic procedures for evaluating expressions, and performing calculations, involving these operations and relations.
The binary operations of set union (
) and intersection (
) satisfy many identities. Several of these identities or "laws" have well established names.
Notation
Throughout this article, capital letters (such as
and
) will denote sets. On the left hand side of an identity, typically,
will be the leftmost set,
will be the middle set, and
will be the rightmost set.
This is to facilitate applying identities to expressions that are complicated or use the same symbols as the identity.[note 1]
For example, the identity
may be read as:
Elementary set operations
For sets
and
define:
and
where the symmetric difference
is sometimes denoted by
and equals:[1][2]
One set
is said to intersect another set
if
Sets that do not intersect are said to be disjoint.
The power set of
is the set of all subsets of
and will be denoted by
Universe set and complement notation
The notation
may be used if
is a subset of some set
that is understood (say from context, or because it is clearly stated what the superset
is).
It is emphasized that the definition of
depends on context. For instance, had
been declared as a subset of
with the sets
and
not necessarily related to each other in any way, then
would likely mean
instead of
If it is needed then unless indicated otherwise, it should be assumed that
denotes the universe set, which means that all sets that are used in the formula are subsets of
In particular, the complement of a set
will be denoted by
where unless indicated otherwise, it should be assumed that
denotes the complement of
in (the universe)
One subset involved
Assume
Identity:
Definition:
is called a left identity element of a binary operator
if
for all
and it is called a right identity element of
if
for all
A left identity element that is also a right identity element if called an identity element.
The empty set
is an identity element of binary union
and symmetric difference
and it is also a right identity element of set subtraction
but
is not a left identity element of
since
so
if and only if
Idempotence
and Nilpotence
:
Domination/Absorbing element:
Definition:
is called a left absorbing element of a binary operator
if
for all
and it is called a right absorbing element of
if
for all
A left absorbing element that is also a right absorbing element if called an absorbing element. Absorbing elements are also sometime called annihilating elements or zero elements.
A universe set is an absorbing element of binary union
The empty set
is an absorbing element of binary intersection
and binary Cartesian product
and it is also a left absorbing element of set subtraction
but
is not a right absorbing element of set subtraction since
where
if and only if
Double complement or involution law:
Two sets involved
In the left hand sides of the following identities,
is the L eft most set and
is the R ight most set.
Assume both
are subsets of some universe set
In the left hand sides of the following identities, L is the L eft most set and R is the R ight most set. Whenever necessary, both L and R should be assumed to be subsets of some universe set X, so that
De Morgan's laws
De Morgan's laws state that for
Commutativity
Unions, intersection, and symmetric difference are commutative operations:
Set subtraction is not commutative. However, the commutativity of set subtraction can be characterized: from
it follows that:
Said differently, if distinct symbols always represented distinct sets, then the only true formulas of the form
that could be written would be those involving a single symbol; that is, those of the form:
But such formulas are necessarily true for every binary operation
(because
must hold by definition of equality), and so in this sense, set subtraction is as diametrically opposite to being commutative as is possible for a binary operation.
Set subtraction is also neither left alternative nor right alternative; instead,
if and only if
if and only if
Set subtraction is quasi-commutative and satisfies the Jordan identity.
Other identities involving two sets
Absorption laws:
Other properties
Intervals:
Subsets ⊆ and supersets ⊇
The following statements are equivalent for any
- Definition of subset: if
then 





and
are disjoint (that is,
)
(that is,
)
The following statements are equivalent for any

- There exists some

Set equality
The following statements are equivalent:



- If
then
if and only if 
- Uniqueness of complements: If
then 
Empty set
A set
is empty if the sentence
is true, where the notation
is shorthand for
If
is any set then the following are equivalent:
is not empty, meaning that the sentence
is true (literally, the logical negation of "
is empty" holds true).
- (In classical mathematics)
is inhabited, meaning:
- In constructive mathematics, "not empty" and "inhabited" are not equivalent: every inhabited set is not empty but the converse is not always guaranteed; that is, in constructive mathematics, a set
that is not empty (where by definition, "
is empty" means that the statement
is true) might not have an inhabitant (which is an
such that
).
for some set 
If
is any set then the following are equivalent:
is empty (
), meaning: 
for every set 
for every set 
for some/every set 

Given any
the following are equivalent:



Moreover,
Meets, Joins, and lattice properties
Inclusion is a partial order:
Explicitly, this means that inclusion
which is a binary operation, has the following three properties:
- Reflexivity:

- Antisymmetry:

- Transitivity:

The following proposition says that for any set
the power set of
ordered by inclusion, is a bounded lattice, and hence together with the distributive and complement laws above, show that it is a Boolean algebra.
Existence of a least element and a greatest element:
Joins/supremums exist:
The union
is the join/supremum of
and
with respect to
because:
and
and
- if
is a set such that
and
then 
The intersection
is the join/supremum of
and
with respect to
Meets/infimums exist:
The intersection
is the meet/infimum of
and
with respect to
because:
- if
and
and
- if
is a set such that
and
then 
The union
is the meet/infimum of
and
with respect to
Other inclusion properties:
- If
then 
- If
and
then 
Three sets involved
In the left hand sides of the following identities,
is the L eft most set,
is the M iddle set, and
is the R ight most set.
Precedence rules
There is no universal agreement on the order of precedence of the basic set operators.
Nevertheless, many authors use precedence rules for set operators, although these rules vary with the author.
One common convention is to associate intersection
with logical conjunction (and)
and associate union
with logical disjunction (or)
and then transfer the precedence of these logical operators (where
has precedence over
) to these set operators, thereby giving
precedence over
So for example,
would mean
since it would be associated with the logical statement
and similarly,
would mean
since it would be associated with
Sometimes, set complement (subtraction)
is also associated with logical complement (not)
in which case it will have the highest precedence.
More specifically,
is rewritten
so that for example,
would mean
since it would be rewritten as the logical statement
which is equal to
For another example, because
means
which is equal to both
and
(where
was rewritten as
), the formula
would refer to the set
moreover, since
this set is also equal to
(other set identities can similarly be deduced from propositional calculus identities in this way).
However, because set subtraction is not associative
a formula such as
would be ambiguous; for this reason, among others, set subtraction is often not assigned any precedence at all.
Symmetric difference
is sometimes associated with exclusive or (xor)
(also sometimes denoted by
), in which case if the order of precedence from highest to lowest is
then the order of precedence (from highest to lowest) for the set operators would be
There is no universal agreement on the precedence of exclusive disjunction
with respect to the other logical connectives, which is why symmetric difference
is not often assigned a precedence.
Associativity
Definition: A binary operator
is called associative if
always holds.
The following set operators are associative:
For set subtraction, instead of associativity, only the following is always guaranteed:
where equality holds if and only if
(this condition does not depend on
). Thus
if and only if
where the only difference between the left and right hand side set equalities is that the locations of
have been swapped.
Distributivity
Definition: If
are binary operators then
left distributes over
if
while
right distributes over
if
The operator
distributes over
if it both left distributes and right distributes over
In the definitions above, to transform one side to the other, the innermost operator (the operator inside the parentheses) becomes the outermost operator and the outermost operator becomes the innermost operator.
Right distributivity:
Left distributivity:
Distributivity and symmetric difference ∆
Intersection distributes over symmetric difference:
Union does not distribute over symmetric difference because only the following is guaranteed in general:
Symmetric difference does not distribute over itself:
and in general, for any sets
(where
represents
),
might not be a subset, nor a superset, of
(and the same is true for
).
Distributivity and set subtraction \
Failure of set subtraction to left distribute:
Set subtraction is right distributive over itself. However, set subtraction is not left distributive over itself because only the following is guaranteed in general:
where equality holds if and only if
which happens if and only if
For symmetric difference, the sets
and
are always disjoint.
So these two sets are equal if and only if they are both equal to
Moreover,
if and only if
To investigate the left distributivity of set subtraction over unions or intersections, consider how the sets involved in (both of) De Morgan's laws are all related:
always holds (the equalities on the left and right are De Morgan's laws) but equality is not guaranteed in general (that is, the containment
might be strict).
Equality holds if and only if
which happens if and only if
This observation about De Morgan's laws shows that
is not left distributive over
or
because only the following are guaranteed in general:
where equality holds for one (or equivalently, for both) of the above two inclusion formulas if and only if
The following statements are equivalent:


that is,
left distributes over
for these three particular sets
that is,
left distributes over
for these three particular sets



and 


Quasi-commutativity:
always holds but in general,
However,
if and only if
if and only if
Set subtraction complexity: To manage the many identities involving set subtraction, this section is divided based on where the set subtraction operation and parentheses are located on the left hand side of the identity. The great variety and (relative) complexity of formulas involving set subtraction (compared to those without it) is in part due to the fact that unlike
and
set subtraction is neither associative nor commutative and it also is not left distributive over
or even over itself.
Two set subtractions
Set subtraction is not associative in general:
since only the following is always guaranteed:
(L\M)\R
L\(M\R)
- If

with equality if and only if 
One set subtraction
(L\M) ⁎ R
Set subtraction on the left, and parentheses on the left

L\(M ⁎ R)
Set subtraction on the left, and parentheses on the right
where the above two sets that are the subjects of De Morgan's laws always satisfy
(L ⁎ M)\R
Set subtraction on the right, and parentheses on the left
L ⁎ (M\R)
Set subtraction on the right, and parentheses on the right

Three operations on three sets
(L • M) ⁎ (M • R)
Operations of the form
:
(L • M) ⁎ (R\M)
Operations of the form
:
(L\M) ⁎ (L\R)
Operations of the form
:
Other simplifications
Other properties:
- If
then 

- If
then 
if and only if for any
belongs to at most two of the sets 
Symmetric difference ∆ of finitely many sets
Given finitely many sets
something belongs to their symmetric difference if and only if it belongs to an odd number of these sets. Explicitly, for any
if and only if the cardinality
is odd. (Recall that symmetric difference is associative so parentheses are not needed for the set
).
Consequently, the symmetric difference of three sets satisfies:
Cartesian products ⨯ of finitely many sets
Binary ⨯ distributes over ⋃ and ⋂ and \ and ∆
The binary Cartesian product ⨯ distributes over unions, intersections, set subtraction, and symmetric difference:
But in general, ⨯ does not distribute over itself:
Binary ⋂ of finite ⨯
Binary ⋃ of finite ⨯
Difference \ of finite ⨯
and
Finite ⨯ of differences \
Symmetric difference ∆ and finite ⨯
In general,
need not be a subset nor a superset of
Arbitrary families of sets
Let
and
be indexed families of sets. Whenever the assumption is needed, then all indexing sets, such as
and
are assumed to be non-empty.
Definitions
A family of sets or (more briefly) a family refers to a set whose elements are sets.
An indexed family of sets is a function from some set, called its indexing set, into some family of sets.
An indexed family of sets will be denoted by
where this notation assigns the symbol
for the indexing set and for every index
assigns the symbol
to the value of the function at
The function itself may then be denoted by the symbol
which is obtained from the notation
by replacing the index
with a bullet symbol
explicitly,
is the function:
which may be summarized by writing
Any given indexed family of sets
(which is a function) can be canonically associated with its image/range
(which is a family of sets).
Conversely, any given family of sets
may be associated with the
-indexed family of sets
which is technically the identity map
However, this is not a bijective correspondence because an indexed family of sets
is not required to be injective (that is, there may exist distinct indices
such as
), which in particular means that it is possible for distinct indexed families of sets (which are functions) to be associated with the same family of sets (by having the same image/range).
Arbitrary unions defined
| | Def. 1 |
If
then
which is somethings called the nullary union convention (despite being called a convention, this equality follows from the definition).
If
is a family of sets then
denotes the set:
Arbitrary intersections defined
If
then
| | Def. 2 |
If
is a non-empty family of sets then
denotes the set:
Nullary intersections
If
then
where every possible thing
in the universe vacuously satisfied the condition: "if
then
". Consequently,
consists of everything in the universe.
So if
and:
- if you are working in a model in which there exists some universe set
then 
- otherwise, if you are working in a model in which "the class of all things
" is not a set (by far the most common situation) then
is undefined because
consists of everything, which makes
a proper class and not a set.
- Assumption: Henceforth, whenever a formula requires some indexing set to be non-empty in order for an arbitrary intersection to be well-defined, then this will automatically be assumed without mention.
A consequence of this is the following assumption/definition:
- A finite intersection of sets or an intersection of finitely many sets refers to the intersection of a finite collection of one or more sets.
Some authors adopt the so called nullary intersection convention, which is the convention that an empty intersection of sets is equal to some canonical set. In particular, if all sets are subsets of some set
then some author may declare that the empty intersection of these sets be equal to
However, the nullary intersection convention is not as commonly accepted as the nullary union convention and this article will not adopt it (this is due to the fact that unlike the empty union, the value of the empty intersection depends on
so if there are multiple sets under consideration, which is commonly the case, then the value of the empty intersection risks becoming ambiguous).
Multiple index sets
Distributing unions and intersections
Binary ⋂ of arbitrary ⋃'s
| | Eq. 3a |
and
| | Eq. 3b |
- If all
are pairwise disjoint and all
are also pairwise disjoint, then so are all
(that is, if
then
).
- Importantly, if
then in general, (an example of this is given below). The single union on the right hand side must be over all pairs
The same is usually true for other similar non-trivial set equalities and relations that depend on two (potentially unrelated) indexing sets
and
(such as Eq. 4b or Eq. 7g). Two exceptions are Eq. 2c (unions of unions) and Eq. 2d (intersections of intersections), but both of these are among the most trivial of set equalities (although even for these equalities there is still something that must be proven[note 2]).
- Example where equality fails: Let
and let
Let
and let
Then Furthermore,
Binary ⋃ of arbitrary ⋂'s
| | Eq. 4a |
and
| | Eq. 4b |
- Importantly, if
then in general, (an example of this is given above). The single intersection on the right hand side must be over all pairs
Arbitrary ⋂'s and arbitrary ⋃'s
Incorrectly distributing by swapping ⋂ and ⋃
Naively swapping
and
may produce a different set
The following inclusion always holds:
| | Inclusion 1 ∪∩ is a subset of ∩∪ |
In general, equality need not hold and moreover, the right hand side depends on how for each fixed
the sets
are labelled; and analogously, the left hand side depends on how for each fixed
the sets
are labelled. An example demonstrating this is now given.
- Example of dependence on labeling and failure of equality: To see why equality need not hold when
and
are swapped, let
and let
and
Then
If
and
are swapped while
and
are unchanged, which gives rise to the sets
and
then
In particular, the left hand side is no longer
which shows that the left hand side
depends on how the sets are labelled.
If instead
and
are swapped while
and
are unchanged, which gives rise to the sets
and
then both the left hand side and right hand side are equal to
which shows that the right hand side also depends on how the sets are labeled.
Equality in Inclusion 1 ∪∩ is a subset of ∩∪ can hold under certain circumstances, such as in 7e, which is the special case where
is
(that is,
with the same indexing sets
and
), or such as in 7f, which is the special case where
is
(that is,
with the indexing sets
and
swapped).
For a correct formula that extends the distributive laws, an approach other than just switching
and
is needed.
Correct distributive laws
Suppose that for each
is a non-empty index set and for each
let
be any set (for example, to apply this law to
use
for all
and use
for all
and all
). Let
denote the Cartesian product, which can be interpreted as the set of all functions
such that
for every
Such a function may also be denoted using the tuple notation
where
for every
and conversely, a tuple
is just notation for the function with domain
whose value at
is
both notations can be used to denote the elements of
Then
| | Eq. 5 ∩∪ to ∪∩ |
| | Eq. 6 ∪∩ to ∩∪ |
where
Applying the distributive laws
Example application: In the particular case where all
are equal (that is,
for all
which is the case with the family
for example), then letting
denote this common set, the Cartesian product will be
which is the set of all functions of the form
The above set equalities Eq. 5 ∩∪ to ∪∩ and Eq. 6 ∪∩ to ∩∪, respectively become:
which when combined with Inclusion 1 ∪∩ is a subset of ∩∪ implies:
where
- on the left hand side, the indices
range over
(so the subscripts of
range over
)
- on the right hand side, the indices
range over
(so the subscripts of
range over
).
Example application: To apply the general formula to the case of
and
use
and let
for all
and let
for all
Every map
can be bijectively identified with the pair
(the inverse sends
to the map
defined by
and
this is technically just a change of notation). Recall that Eq. 5 ∩∪ to ∪∩ was
Expanding and simplifying the left hand side gives
and doing the same to the right hand side gives:
Thus the general identity Eq. 5 ∩∪ to ∪∩ reduces down to the previously given set equality Eq. 3b:
Distributing subtraction over ⋃ and ⋂
| | Eq. 7a |
| | Eq. 7b |
The next identities are known as De Morgan's laws.
| | Eq. 7c |
| | Eq. 7d |
The following four set equalities can be deduced from the equalities 7a - 7d above.
| | Eq. 7e |
| | Eq. 7f |
| | Eq. 7g |
| | Eq. 7h |
In general, naively swapping
and
may produce a different set (see this note for more details).
The equalities
found in Eq. 7e and Eq. 7f are thus unusual in that they state exactly that swapping
and
will not change the resulting set.
Commutativity and associativity of ⋃ and ⋂
Commutativity:
Unions of unions and intersections of intersections:
and
| | Eq. 2a |
| | Eq. 2b |
and if
then also:[note 2]
| | Eq. 2c |
| | Eq. 2d |
Cartesian products Π of arbitrarily many sets
Intersections ⋂ of Π
If
is a family of sets then
| | Eq. 8 |
- Moreover, a tuple
belongs to the set in Eq. 8 above if and only if
for all
and all 
In particular, if
and
are two families indexed by the same set then
So for instance,
and
Intersections of products indexed by different sets
Let
and
be two families indexed by different sets.
Technically,
implies
However, sometimes these products are somehow identified as the same set through some bijection or one of these products is identified as a subset of the other via some injective map, in which case (by abuse of notation) this intersection may be equal to some other (possibly non-empty) set.
- For example, if
and
with all sets equal to
then
and
where
unless, for example,
is identified as a subset of
through some injection, such as maybe
for instance; however, in this particular case the product
actually represents the
-indexed product
where 
- For another example, take
and
with
and
all equal to
Then
and
which can both be identified as the same set via the bijection that sends
to
Under this identification, 
Binary ⨯ distributes over arbitrary ⋃ and ⋂
The binary Cartesian product ⨯ distributes over arbitrary intersections (when the indexing set is not empty) and over arbitrary unions:
Distributing arbitrary Π over arbitrary ⋃
Suppose that for each
is a non-empty index set and for each
let
be any set (for example, to apply this law to
use
for all
and use
for all
and all
). Let
denote the Cartesian product, which (as mentioned above) can be interpreted as the set of all functions
such that
for every
.
Then
| | Eq. 11 Π∪ to ∪Π |
where
Unions ⋃ of Π
For unions, only the following is guaranteed in general:
where
is a family of sets.
- Example where equality fails: Let
let
let
and let
Then More generally,
if and only if for each
at least one of the sets in the
-indexed collections of sets
is empty, while
if and only if for each
at least one of the sets in the
-indexed collections of sets
is not empty.
However,
Difference \ of Π
If
and
are two families of sets then:
so for instance,
and
Symmetric difference ∆ of Π
Functions and sets
Let
be any function.
Let
be completely arbitrary sets. Assume
Definitions
Let
be any function, where we denote its domain
by
and denote its codomain
by
Many of the identities below do not actually require that the sets be somehow related to
's domain or codomain (that is, to
or
) so when some kind of relationship is necessary then it will be clearly indicated.
Because of this, in this article, if
is declared to be "any set," and it is not indicated that
must be somehow related to
or
(say for instance, that it be a subset
or
) then it is meant that
is truly arbitrary.[note 3]
This generality is useful in situations where
is a map between two subsets
and
of some larger sets
and
and where the set
might not be entirely contained in
and/or
(e.g. if all that is known about
is that
); in such a situation it may be useful to know what can and cannot be said about
and/or
without having to introduce a (potentially unnecessary) intersection such as:
and/or
Images and preimages of sets
If
is any set then the image of
under
is defined to be the set:
while the preimage of
under
is:
where if
is a singleton set then the fiber or preimage of
under
is
Denote by
or
the image or range of
which is the set:
Saturated sets
A set
is said to be
-saturated or a saturated set if any of the following equivalent conditions are satisfied:
- There exists a set
such that
- Any such set
necessarily contains
as a subset.
- Any set not entirely contained in the domain of
cannot be
-saturated.

and
- The inclusion
always holds, where if
then this becomes 
and if
and
satisfy
then
- Whenever a fiber of
intersects
then
contains the entire fiber. In other words,
contains every
-fiber that intersects it.
- Explicitly: whenever
is such that
then 
- In both this statement and the next, the set
may be replaced with any superset of
(such as
) and the resulting statement will still be equivalent to the rest.
- The intersection of
with a fiber of
is equal to the empty set or to the fiber itself.
- Explicitly: for every
the intersection
is equal to the empty set
or to
(that is,
or
).
For a set
to be
-saturated, it is necessary that
Compositions and restrictions of functions
If
and
are maps then
denotes the composition map
with domain and codomain
defined by
The restriction of
to
denoted by
is the map
with
defined by sending
to
that is,
Alternatively,
where
denotes the inclusion map, which is defined by
(Pre)Images of arbitrary unions ⋃'s and intersections ⋂'s
If
is a family of arbitrary sets indexed by
then:
So of these four identities, it is only images of intersections that are not always preserved. Preimages preserve all basic set operations. Unions are preserved by both images and preimages.
If all
are
-saturated then
be will be
-saturated and equality will hold in the first relation above; explicitly, this means:
| | Conditional Equality 10a |
If
is a family of arbitrary subsets of
which means that
for all
then Conditional Equality 10a becomes:
| | Conditional Equality 10b |
(Pre)Images of binary set operations
Throughout, let
and
be any sets and let
be any function.
Summary
As the table below shows, set equality is not guaranteed only for images of: intersections, set subtractions, and symmetric differences.
Image
|
Preimage
|
Additional assumptions on sets
|
[6]
|
|
None
|
|
|
None
|
|
|
None
|
|
[note 4]
|
None
|
|
|
None
|
Preimages preserve set operations
Preimages of sets are well-behaved with respect to all basic set operations:
In words, preimages distribute over unions, intersections, set subtraction, and symmetric difference.
Images only preserve unions
Images of unions are well-behaved:
but images of the other basic set operations are not since only the following are guaranteed in general:
In words, images distribute over unions but not necessarily over intersections, set subtraction, or symmetric difference. What these latter three operations have in common is set subtraction: they either are set subtraction
or else they can naturally be defined as the set subtraction of two sets:
If
then
where as in the more general case, equality is not guaranteed. If
is surjective then
which can be rewritten as:
if
and
Counter-examples: images of operations not distributing
If
is constant,
and
then all four of the set containments
are strict/proper (that is, the sets are not equal) since one side is the empty set while the other is non-empty. Thus equality is not guaranteed for even the simplest of functions.
The example above is now generalized to show that these four set equalities can fail for any constant function whose domain contains at least two (distinct) points.
Example: Let
be any constant function with image
and suppose that
are non-empty disjoint subsets; that is,
and
which implies that all of the sets
and
are not empty and so consequently, their images under
are all equal to
- The containment
is strict:
In words: functions might not distribute over set subtraction
- The containment
is strict:
- The containment
is strict:
In words: functions might not distribute over symmetric difference
(which can be defined as the set subtraction of two sets:
).
- The containment
is strict:
In words: functions might not distribute over set intersection
(which can be defined as the set subtraction of two sets:
).
What the set operations in these four examples have in common is that they either are set subtraction
(examples (1) and (2)) or else they can naturally be defined as the set subtraction of two sets (examples (3) and (4)).
Mnemonic: In fact, for each of the above four set formulas for which equality is not guaranteed, the direction of the containment (that is, whether to use
) can always be deduced by imagining the function
as being constant and the two sets (
and
) as being non-empty disjoint subsets of its domain. This is because every equality fails for such a function and sets: one side will be always be
and the other non-empty − from this fact, the correct choice of
can be deduced by answering: "which side is empty?" For example, to decide if the
in
should be
pretend[note 5]
that
is constant and that
and
are non-empty disjoint subsets of
's domain; then the left hand side would be empty (since
), which indicates that
should be
(the resulting statement is always guaranteed to be true) because this is the choice that will make
true.
Alternatively, the correct direction of containment can also be deduced by consideration of any constant
with
and
Furthermore, this mnemonic can also be used to correctly deduce whether or not a set operation always distribute over images or preimages; for example, to determine whether or not
always equals
or alternatively, whether or not
always equals
(although
was used here, it can replaced by
). The answer to such a question can, as before, be deduced by consideration of this constant function: the answer for the general case (that is, for arbitrary
and
) is always the same as the answer for this choice of (constant) function and disjoint non-empty sets.
Conditions guaranteeing that images distribute over set operations
Characterizations of when equality holds for all sets:
For any function
the following statements are equivalent:
is injective.
- This means:
for all distinct 
(The equals sign
can be replaced with
).
(The equals sign
can be replaced with
).
(The equals sign
can be replaced with
).
(The equals sign
can be replaced with
).
- Any one of the four statements (b) - (e) but with the words "for all" replaced with any one of the following:
- "for all singleton subsets"
- In particular, the statement that results from (d) gives a characterization of injectivity that explicitly involves only one point (rather than two):
is injective if and only if 
- "for all disjoint singleton subsets"
- For statement (d), this is the same as: "for all singleton subsets" (because the definition of "pairwise disjoint" is satisfies vacuously by any family that consists of exactly 1 set).
- "for all disjoint subsets"
In particular, if a map is not known to be injective then barring additional information, there is no guarantee that any of the equalities in statements (b) - (e) hold.
An example above can be used to help prove this characterization. Indeed, comparison of that example with such a proof suggests that the example is representative of the fundamental reason why one of these four equalities in statements (b) - (e) might not hold (that is, representative of "what goes wrong" when a set equality does not hold).
Conditions for f(L⋂R) = f(L)⋂f(R)
Characterizations of equality: The following statements are equivalent:


- The left hand side
is always equal to
(because
always holds).



- If
satisfies
then 
- If
but
then 



- Any of the above three conditions (i) - (k) but with the subset symbol
replaced with an equals sign 
Sufficient conditions for equality: Equality holds if any of the following are true:
is injective.[7]
- The restriction
is injective.
[note 6]
is
-saturated; that is,
[note 6]
is
-saturated; that is, 


or equivalently, 
or equivalently, 
or equivalently, 




In addition, the following always hold:
Conditions for f(L\R) = f(L)\f(R)
Characterizations of equality: The following statements are equivalent:[proof 1]




- Whenever
then 
- The set on the right hand side is always equal to

- This is the above condition (f) but with the subset symbol
replaced with an equals sign 
Necessary conditions for equality (excluding characterizations): If equality holds then the following are necessarily true:
or equivalently 
or equivalently, 

Sufficient conditions for equality: Equality holds if any of the following are true:
is injective.
- The restriction
is injective.
[note 6] or equivalently, 
is
-saturated; that is,
[note 6]
or equivalently, 
Conditions for f(X\R) = f(X)\f(R)
Characterizations of equality: The following statements are equivalent:[proof 1]




is
-saturated.
- Whenever
then 


where if
then this list can be extended to include:
is
-saturated; that is, 
Sufficient conditions for equality: Equality holds if any of the following are true:
is injective.
is
-saturated; that is, 
Conditions for f(L∆R) = f(L)∆f(R)
Characterizations of equality: The following statements are equivalent:


and 
and 
and
- The inclusions
and
always hold.
- If this above set equality holds, then this set will also be equal to both
and 
and 
Necessary conditions for equality (excluding characterizations): If equality holds then the following are necessarily true:
or equivalently 

Sufficient conditions for equality: Equality holds if any of the following are true:
is injective.
- The restriction
is injective.
For any function
and any sets
and
[proof 2]
Taking
in the above formulas gives:
where the set
is equal to the image under
of the largest
-saturated subset of
- In general, only
always holds and equality is not guaranteed; but replacing "
" with its subset "
" results in a formula in which equality is always guaranteed:
From this it follows that:[proof 1]
- If
then
which can be written more symmetrically as
(since
).
It follows from
and the above formulas for the image of a set subtraction that for any function
and any sets
and
It follows from the above formulas for the image of a set subtraction that for any function
and any set
This is more easily seen as being a consequence of the fact that for any
if and only if
It follows from the above formulas for the image of a set that for any function
and any sets
and
where moreover, for any
if and only if
if and only if
if and only if 
The sets
and
mentioned above could, in particular, be any of the sets
or
for example.
(Pre)Images of set operations on (pre)images
Let
and
be arbitrary sets,
be any map, and let
and
(Pre)Images of operations on images
Since
Since
Using
this becomes
and
and so
(Pre)Images and Cartesian products Π
Let
and for every
let
denote the canonical projection onto
Definitions
Given a collection of maps
indexed by
define the map
which is also denoted by
This is the unique map satisfying
Conversely, if given a map then
Explicitly, what this means is that if
is defined for every
then
the unique map satisfying:
for all
or said more briefly,
The map
should not be confused with the Cartesian product
of these maps, which is by definition is the map
with domain
rather than
Preimage and images of a Cartesian product
Suppose
If
then
If
then
where equality will hold if
in which case
and
| | Eq. 11a |
For equality to hold, it suffices for there to exist a family
of subsets
such that
in which case:
| | Eq. 11b |
and
for all
(Pre)Image of a single set
Image
|
Preimage
|
Additional assumptions
|
|
|
None
|
|
|
None
|
|
|
None
|
|
|
None
|
|
|
None
|
|
|
None ( and are arbitrary functions).
|

|
|
None
|
|
|
None
|
|
|
None
|
Containments ⊆ and intersections ⋂ of images and preimages
Equivalences and implications of images and preimages
Intersection of a set and a (pre)image
The following statements are equivalent:




Thus for any
Sequences and collections of families of sets
Definitions
A family of sets or simply a family is a set whose elements are sets.
A family over
is a family of subsets of
The power set of a set
is the set of all subsets of
:
Notation for sequences of sets
Throughout,
will be arbitrary sets and
and will denote a net or a sequence of sets where if it is a sequence then this will be indicated by either of the notations
where
denotes the natural numbers.
A notation
indicates that
is a net directed by
which (by definition) is a sequence if the set
which is called the net's indexing set, is the natural numbers (that is, if
) and
is the natural order on
Disjoint and monotone sequences of sets
If
for all distinct indices
then
is called a pairwise disjoint or simply a disjoint.
A sequence or net
of set is called increasing or non-decreasing if (resp. decreasing or non-increasing) if for all indices
(resp.
).
A sequence or net
of set is called strictly increasing (resp. strictly decreasing) if it is non-decreasing (resp. is non-increasing) and also
for all distinct indices
It is called monotone if it is non-decreasing or non-increasing and it is called strictly monotone if it is strictly increasing or strictly decreasing.
A sequences or net
is said to increase to
denoted by
or
if
is increasing and the union of all
is
that is, if
It is said to decrease to
denoted by
or
if
is increasing and the intersection of all
is
that is, if
Definitions of elementwise operations on families
If
are families of sets and if
is any set then define:
which are respectively called elementwise union, elementwise intersection, elementwise (set) difference, elementwise symmetric difference, and the trace/restriction of
to
The regular union, intersection, and set difference are all defined as usual and are denoted with their usual notation:
and
respectively.
These elementwise operations on families of sets play an important role in, among other subjects, the theory of filters and prefilters on sets.
The upward closure in
of a family
is the family:
and the downward closure of
is the family:
Definitions of categories of families of sets
The following table lists some well-known categories of families of sets having applications in general topology and measure theory.
Families of sets over
|
Is necessarily true of  or, is closed under:
|
Directed by
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
F.I.P.
|
π-system
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
Semiring
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
Never
|
Semialgebra (Semifield)
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
Never
|
Monotone class
|
|
|
|
|
|
only if  |
only if  |
|
|
|
𝜆-system (Dynkin System)
|
|
|
|
only if
 |
|
|
only if or they are disjoint |
|
|
Never
|
Ring (Order theory)
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
Ring (Measure theory)
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
Never
|
δ-Ring
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
Never
|
𝜎-Ring
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
Never
|
Algebra (Field)
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
Never
|
𝜎-Algebra (𝜎-Field)
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
Never
|
Dual ideal
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
Filter
|
|
|
|
Never |
Never |
|
|
|
 |
|
Prefilter (Filter base)
|
|
|
|
Never |
Never |
|
|
|
 |
|
Filter subbase
|
|
|
|
Never |
Never |
|
|
|
 |
|
Open Topology
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
(even arbitrary ) |
|
|
Never
|
Closed Topology
|
|
|
|
|
|
(even arbitrary ) |
|
|
|
Never
|
Is necessarily true of  or, is closed under:
|
directed downward
|
finite intersections
|
finite unions
|
relative complements
|
complements in
|
countable intersections
|
countable unions
|
contains
|
contains
|
Finite Intersection Property
|
Additionally, a semiring is a π-system where every complement is equal to a finite disjoint union of sets in 
A semialgebra is a semiring where every complement is equal to a finite disjoint union of sets in 
are arbitrary elements of and it is assumed that 
|
A family
is called isotone, ascending, or upward closed in
if
and
A family
is called downward closed if
A family
is said to be:
- closed under finite intersections (resp. closed under finite unions) if whenever
then
(respectively,
).
- closed under countable intersections (resp. closed under countable unions) if whenever
are elements of
then so is their intersections
(resp. so is their union
).
- closed under complementation in (or with respect to)
if whenever
then 
A family
of sets is called a/an:
- π−system if
and
is closed under finite-intersections.
- Every non-empty family
is contained in a unique smallest (with respect to
) π−system that is denoted by
and called the π−system generated by 
- filter subbase and is said to have the finite intersection property if
and 
- filter on
if
is a family of subsets of
that is a π−system, is upward closed in
and is also proper, which by definition means that it does not contain the empty set as an element.
- prefilter or filter base if it is a non-empty family of subsets of some set
whose upward closure in
is a filter on 
- algebra on
is a non-empty family of subsets of
that contains the empty set, forms a π−system, and is also closed under complementation with respect to 
- σ-algebra on
is an algebra on
that is closed under countable unions (or equivalently, closed under countable intersections).
Sequences of sets often arise in measure theory.
Algebra of sets
A family
of subsets of a set
is said to be an algebra of sets if
and for all
all three of the sets
and
are elements of
[13]
The article on this topic lists set identities and other relationships these three operations.
Every algebra of sets is also a ring of sets[13] and a π-system.
Algebra generated by a family of sets
Given any family
of subsets of
there is a unique smallest[note 7] algebra of sets in
containing
[13]
It is called the algebra generated by
and it will be denote it by
This algebra can be constructed as follows:[13]
- If
then
and we are done. Alternatively, if
is empty then
may be replaced with
and continue with the construction.
- Let
be the family of all sets in
together with their complements (taken in
).
- Let
be the family of all possible finite intersections of sets in
[note 8]
- Then the algebra generated by
is the set
consisting of all possible finite unions of sets in 
Elementwise operations on families
Let
and
be families of sets over
On the left hand sides of the following identities,
is the L eft most family,
is in the M iddle, and
is the R ight most set.
Commutativity:
Associativity:
Identity:
Domination:
Power set
If
and
are subsets of a vector space
and if
is a scalar then
Sequences of sets
Suppose that
is any set such that
for every index
If
decreases to
then
increases to
whereas if instead
increases to
then
decreases to
If
are arbitrary sets and if
increases (resp. decreases) to
then
increase (resp. decreases) to
Partitions
Suppose that
is any sequence of sets, that
is any subset, and for every index
let
Then
and
is a sequence of pairwise disjoint sets.
Suppose that
is non-decreasing, let
and let
for every
Then
and
is a sequence of pairwise disjoint sets.
See also
Notes
Notes
- ^
For example, the expression
uses two of the same symbols (
and
) that appear in the identity
but they refer to different sets in each expression.
To apply this identity to
substitute
and
(since these are the left, middle, and right sets in
) to obtain:
For a second example, this time applying the identity to
is now given. The identity
can be applied to
by reading
and
as
and
and then substituting
and
to obtain:
- ^ a b To deduce Eq. 2c from Eq. 2a, it must still be shown that
so Eq. 2c is not a completely immediate consequence of Eq. 2a. (Compare this to the commentary about Eq. 3b).
- ^ So for instance, it's even possible that
or that
and
(which happens, for instance, if
), etc.
- ^ The conclusion
can also be written as:
- ^ Whether or not it is even feasible for the function
to be constant and the sets
and
to be non-empty and disjoint is irrelevant for reaching the correct conclusion about whether to use
- ^ a b c d Note that this condition depends entirely on
and not on
- ^ Here "smallest" means relative to subset containment. So if
is any algebra of sets containing
then
- ^ Since
there is some
such that its complement also belongs to
The intersection of these two sets implies that
The union of these two sets is equal to
which implies that
Proofs
- ^ a b c Let
where because
is also equal to
As proved above,
so that
if and only if
Since
this happens if and only if
Because
are both subsets of
the condition on the right hand side happens if and only if
Because
the equality
holds if and only if
If
(such as when
or
) then
if and only if
In particular, taking
proves:
if and only if
where
- ^ Let
and let
denote the set equality
which will now be proven. If
then
so there exists some
now
implies
so that
To prove the reverse inclusion
let
so that there exists some
such that
Then
so that
and thus
which proves that
as desired.
Defining
the identity
follows from
and the inclusions
Citations
References
- Artin, Michael (1991). Algebra. Prentice Hall. ISBN 81-203-0871-9.
- Blyth, T.S. (2005). Lattices and Ordered Algebraic Structures. Springer. ISBN 1-85233-905-5..
- Bylinski, Czeslaw (2004). "Some Basic Properties of Sets". Journal of Formalized Mathematics. 1. Retrieved 5 October 2021.
- Courant, Richard, Herbert Robbins, Ian Stewart, What is mathematics?: An Elementary Approach to Ideas and Methods, Oxford University Press US, 1996. ISBN 978-0-19-510519-3. "SUPPLEMENT TO CHAPTER II THE ALGEBRA OF SETS".
- Császár, Ákos (1978). General topology. Translated by Császár, Klára. Bristol England: Adam Hilger Ltd. ISBN 0-85274-275-4. OCLC 4146011.
- Dixmier, Jacques (1984). General Topology. Undergraduate Texts in Mathematics. Translated by Berberian, S. K. New York: Springer-Verlag. ISBN 978-0-387-90972-1. OCLC 10277303.
- Dolecki, Szymon; Mynard, Frédéric (2016). Convergence Foundations Of Topology. New Jersey: World Scientific Publishing Company. ISBN 978-981-4571-52-4. OCLC 945169917.
- Dugundji, James (1966). Topology. Boston: Allyn and Bacon. ISBN 978-0-697-06889-7. OCLC 395340485.
- Durrett, Richard (2019). Probability: Theory and Examples (PDF). Cambridge Series in Statistical and Probabilistic Mathematics. Vol. 49 (5th ed.). Cambridge New York, NY: Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-1-108-47368-2. OCLC 1100115281. Retrieved November 5, 2020.
- Halmos, Paul R. (1960). Naive set theory. The University Series in Undergraduate Mathematics. van Nostrand Company. ISBN 9780442030643. Zbl 0087.04403.
- Joshi, K. D. (1983). Introduction to General Topology. New York: John Wiley and Sons Ltd. ISBN 978-0-85226-444-7. OCLC 9218750.
- Kelley, John L. (1985). General Topology. Graduate Texts in Mathematics. Vol. 27 (2 ed.). Birkhäuser. ISBN 978-0-387-90125-1.
- Köthe, Gottfried (1983) [1969]. Topological Vector Spaces I. Grundlehren der mathematischen Wissenschaften. Vol. 159. Translated by Garling, D.J.H. New York: Springer Science & Business Media. ISBN 978-3-642-64988-2. MR 0248498. OCLC 840293704.
- Monk, James Donald (1969). Introduction to Set Theory (PDF). International series in pure and applied mathematics. New York: McGraw-Hill. ISBN 978-0-07-042715-0. OCLC 1102.
- Munkres, James R. (2000). Topology (2nd ed.). Upper Saddle River, NJ: Prentice Hall, Inc. ISBN 978-0-13-181629-9. OCLC 42683260. (accessible to patrons with print disabilities)
- Narici, Lawrence; Beckenstein, Edward (2011). Topological Vector Spaces. Pure and applied mathematics (Second ed.). Boca Raton, FL: CRC Press. ISBN 978-1584888666. OCLC 144216834.
- Padlewska, Beata (1990). "Families of Sets". Journal of Formalized Mathematics. 1: 1. Retrieved 5 October 2021.
- Schechter, Eric (1996). Handbook of Analysis and Its Foundations. San Diego, CA: Academic Press. ISBN 978-0-12-622760-4. OCLC 175294365.
- Schubert, Horst (1968). Topology. London: Macdonald & Co. ISBN 978-0-356-02077-8. OCLC 463753.
- Stoll, Robert R.; Set Theory and Logic, Mineola, N.Y.: Dover Publications (1979) ISBN 0-486-63829-4. "The Algebra of Sets", pp 16—23.
- Trybulec, Zinaida (2002). "Properties of subsets" (PDF). Journal of Formalized Mathematics. 1: 1. Retrieved 5 October 2021.
- Wilansky, Albert (2013). Modern Methods in Topological Vector Spaces. Mineola, New York: Dover Publications, Inc. ISBN 978-0-486-49353-4. OCLC 849801114.
- Willard, Stephen (2004) [1970]. General Topology. Mineola, N.Y.: Dover Publications. ISBN 978-0-486-43479-7. OCLC 115240.
External links