In category theory, a branch of mathematics, the image of a morphism is a generalization of the image of a function.
General definition
Given a category
and a morphism
in
, the image[1]
of
is a monomorphism
satisfying the following universal property:
- There exists a morphism
such that
.
- For any object
with a morphism
and a monomorphism
such that
, there exists a unique morphism
such that
.
Remarks:
- such a factorization does not necessarily exist.
is unique by definition of
monic.
, therefore
by
monic.
is monic.
already implies that
is unique.
The image of
is often denoted by
or
.
Proposition: If
has all equalizers then the
in the factorization
of (1) is an epimorphism.[2]
Proof
Let
be such that
, one needs to show that
. Since the equalizer of
exists,
factorizes as
with
monic. But then
is a factorization of
with
monomorphism. Hence by the universal property of the image there exists a unique arrow
such that
and since
is monic
. Furthermore, one has
and by the monomorphism property of
one obtains
.
This means that
and thus that
equalizes
, whence
.
Second definition
In a category
with all finite limits and colimits, the image is defined as the equalizer
of the so-called cokernel pair
, which is the cocartesian of a morphism with itself over its domain, which will result in a pair of morphisms
, on which the equalizer is taken, i.e. the first of the following diagrams is cocartesian, and the second equalizing.[3]
Remarks:
- Finite bicompleteness of the category ensures that pushouts and equalizers exist.
can be called regular image as
is a regular monomorphism, i.e. the equalizer of a pair of morphisms. (Recall also that an equalizer is automatically a monomorphism).
- In an abelian category, the cokernel pair property can be written
and the equalizer condition
. Moreover, all monomorphisms are regular.
Theorem—If
always factorizes through regular monomorphisms, then the two definitions coincide.
Proof
First definition implies the second: Assume that (1) holds with
regular monomorphism.
- Equalization: one needs to show that
. As the cokernel pair of
and by previous proposition, since
has all equalizers, the arrow
in the factorization
is an epimorphism, hence
.
- Universality: in a category with all colimits (or at least all pushouts)
itself admits a cokernel pair 
- Moreover, as a regular monomorphism,
is the equalizer of a pair of morphisms
but we claim here that it is also the equalizer of
.
- Indeed, by construction
thus the "cokernel pair" diagram for
yields a unique morphism
such that
. Now, a map
which equalizes
also satisfies
, hence by the equalizer diagram for
, there exists a unique map
such that
.
- Finally, use the cokernel pair diagram (of
) with
: there exists a unique
such that
. Therefore, any map
which equalizes
also equalizes
and thus uniquely factorizes as
. This exactly means that
is the equalizer of
.
Second definition implies the first:
- Factorization: taking
in the equalizer diagram (
corresponds to
), one obtains the factorization
.
- Universality: let
be a factorization with
regular monomorphism, i.e. the equalizer of some pair
.
- Then
so that by the "cokernel pair" diagram (of
), with
, there exists a unique
such that
.
- Now, from
(m from the equalizer of (i1, i2) diagram), one obtains
, hence by the universality in the (equalizer of (d1, d2) diagram, with f replaced by m), there exists a unique
such that
.
Examples
In the category of sets the image of a morphism
is the inclusion from the ordinary image
to
. In many concrete categories such as groups, abelian groups and (left- or right) modules, the image of a morphism is the image of the correspondent morphism in the category of sets.
In any normal category with a zero object and kernels and cokernels for every morphism, the image of a morphism
can be expressed as follows:
- im f = ker coker f
In an abelian category (which is in particular binormal), if f is a monomorphism then f = ker coker f, and so f = im f.
Essential Image
A related notion to image is essential image.[4]
A subcategory
of a (strict) category is said to be replete if for every
, and for every isomorphism
, both
and
belong to C.
Given a functor
between categories, the smallest replete subcategory of the target n-category B containing the image of A under F.
See also
References
- ^ Mitchell, Barry (1965), Theory of categories, Pure and applied mathematics, vol. 17, Academic Press, ISBN 978-0-12-499250-4, MR 0202787 Section I.10 p.12
- ^ Mitchell, Barry (1965), Theory of categories, Pure and applied mathematics, vol. 17, Academic Press, ISBN 978-0-12-499250-4, MR 0202787 Proposition 10.1 p.12
- ^ Kashiwara, Masaki; Schapira, Pierre (2006), "Categories and Sheaves", Grundlehren der Mathematischen Wissenschaften, vol. 332, Berlin Heidelberg: Springer, pp. 113–114 Definition 5.1.1
- ^ "essential image in nLab". ncatlab.org. Retrieved 2024-11-15.